Hertje_-_Schumpeter_and_methodological_individualism.pdf

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

  • 8/9/2019 Hertje_-_Schumpeter_and_methodological_individualism.pdf

    1/4

    DOI: 10.1007/s00191-004-0202-3J Evol Econ (2004) 14: 153156

    c Springer-Verlag 2004

    Schumpeter and methodological individualism

    Arnold Heertje

    University of Amsterdam, Faculty of Economics and Econometrics, Roetersstraat 11,

    1018 WB Amsterdam, The Netherlands (e-mail: [email protected])

    It is without doubt that Schumpeter wrote a masterpiece as a young man (Schum-

    peter, 1908). In this book, only ten pages are devoted to methodological individ-

    ualism. This is an interesting theme, which I would like to deal with in this short

    note, written in honor of our precious and warm friend, Mark Perlman. Schumpeter

    starts with a few remarks on the homo economicus, but he does not return to hisobservations on methodological individualism in the later chapters of this book.

    Schumpeter does not consider the acting human being, but looks at the goods in

    his possession (Schumpeter, 1908: p. 86). Still, he observes that the essence of this

    distinction is the goods that belong to an individual. This individualistic approach

    is called Atomismus, following in the footsteps of Carl Menger (Menger, 1883,

    pp. 8289). Schumpeter considered it necessary to make a sharp distinction between

    political and methodological individualism:

    Both concepts have nothing in common. The first refers to general statements

    like the freedom of people to develop themselves and to take part in well-being andto follow practical rules. The second does not include any proposition and does not

    involve a specific starting point. It just means that one starts from the individual in

    order to describe certain economic relationships (Schumpeter: 1908, pp. 9091).

    Schumpeter restricts himself to a more or less vague description of the concept

    of methodological individualism. Again and again, he emphasizes that the applica-

    tion of this insight is part of pure theory or pure economics, which is restricted to

    the analysis of goods that belong to individuals. In Schumpeters hands, method-

    ological individualism restricts itself to the relationship of prices and the behavior

    of individuals. With individualism, one cannot enter the fields of sociology and the

    theory of organization.

    Schumpeters interpretation of methodological individualism conceals a dou-

    ble restriction. First, it is concerned with pure economics. Second, pure economics

    only refers to the analysis of flows of goods. This fact explains why the concept

    does not show up in other works by Schumpeter. One would expect the application

  • 8/9/2019 Hertje_-_Schumpeter_and_methodological_individualism.pdf

    2/4

    154 A. Heertje

    of methodological individualism to the theory of economic development, innova-

    tion, bureaucracy and democracy, but these applications are outside the narrow

    framework that Schumpeter has chosen for this interpretation of methodological

    individualism. In hisHistory of Economic Analysis, Schumpeter calls this frame of

    reference the logic of economic mechanisms (Schumpeter, 1954, p. 889). Schum-peters use of the adjective methodological can only be understood against the

    background of his view on the character of economics. In the literature, the over-

    whelming consensus is to look at methodological individualism as a general method

    of explanation, according to which the individual is the starting point for the ex-

    planation. In at least two respects, this interpretation differs from Schumpeter. The

    economic aspect is not restricted to the possession of goods, but is related to the sat-

    isfaction of wants, insofar as this is as dependent on the allocation of scarce means

    of production, often analyzed in terms of the maximization of welfare under side

    conditions. Furthermore, individuals are not only consumers and producers in themarket, but also politicians, civil servants, bureaucrats, criminals, or tax evaders,

    and others whose behavior can be explained with the help of modern economic

    analysis. While Schumpeters broad view of economic and social relationships has

    contributed to insights into the role of entrepreneurs, innovators, bureaucrats, intel-

    lectuals and politicians, his narrow interpretation of methodological individualism,

    in fact, blocked the analysis of the rich pattern of individuals acting in real life.

    In other words, Schumpeter remained far removed from the hypothesis that

    relates the analysis of social phenomena to the optimizing behavior of individuals

    in the public and private sector. The implication of this is that the specificationof the assumed behavior may differ according to the role that individuals, such as

    entrepreneurs and civil servants, play in society. These specifications can all be

    derived from methodological individualism.

    This conclusion is surprising, as Schumpeter could have built upon Mengers

    book of 1883. Using the term Atomismus, Menger presents a broad interpretation

    of methodological individualism. He observes that social phenomena must be linked

    to the infinite number of individual economic decisions by consumers, producers

    and owners of the factors of production (Menger, 1883, p. 87). Later in his book, he

    applies this reasoning to the emergence of money in a barter economy by referring tothe economic behavior of individuals who look for benefits (Menger, 1883, p. 177).

    Schumpeter, in his book of 1908, does not mention Menger at all. Do we have

    to explain this by the fact that Mengers approach, and the school that formed

    around it, remained excluded from the university curriculum well into the 20th

    century (Vaughn, 1987, p. 442)? Or, must we assume that Schumpeter, without

    further discussion, intentionally deviated from Mengers point of view? Looking

    at Schumpeters obituary of Menger in 1921, it is notable that Schumpeter had a

    very high regard for his contribution to the methodology of the social sciences. I

    am, therefore, inclined to answer the first question in the negative and the second

    in the positive. Whatever may be the answers to these questions, under the flag

    of Schumpeters terminology methodological individualism, modern economic

    theory follows the broad interpretation of Menger, and disregards the narrow and

    very peculiar view of Schumpeter. In other words, Machlup bestows too much

    praise on Schumpeter in writing, with respect to methodological individualism, of

  • 8/9/2019 Hertje_-_Schumpeter_and_methodological_individualism.pdf

    3/4

    Schumpeter and methodological individualism 155

    a Schumpeterian innovation which was fully successful in the sense that it has been

    explicitly accepted by some and implicitly by practically all modern economists

    (Machlup, 1978, p. 47).

    If Schumpeter himself had followed the footsteps of Menger from the beginning,

    his theories on economic development and democracy would have been phrasedin terms of methodological individualism in the modern sense of the terminology.

    His colorful description of the entrepreneur as an innovator of new markets, new

    methods of production, new products and new methods of organization would

    then have been enriched with a characteristic analytical dimension. Further, his

    description of democracy as . . . that institutional arrangement for arriving at

    political decisions in which individuals acquire the power to decide by means of

    a competitive struggle for the peoples vote, could be conceived as an excellent

    starting point for a thorough and broad view on methodological individualism.

    (Schumpeter, 1942, p. 269). Downs refers to Schumpeter as a major source for hisnew theory of democracy (Downs, 1957, p. 89). Although Downs applies the basic

    idea behind methodological individualism, he does not use the concept at all.

    The founders of modern public-choice theory, the Americans James Buchanan

    and Gordon Tullock, choose explicitly methodological individualism as the point of

    departure for their analysis, without ever mentioning Schumpeter. Their treatment

    of the logical foundations of constitutional democracy . . . begins with the acting

    or decision-making individual as he participates in the processes through which

    group choices are organized (Buchanan and Tullock, 1962, p. 1). For this reason,

    their theory is methodologically individualistic. Buchanan (1975) did enlarge anddeepen the analysis in his work on the limits of liberty, in which methodological

    individualism is a cornerstone. He introduced this basic starting point not only

    in economics on a broad scale, but also in political science. He did not dare to

    develop a theory of human behavior, but instead restricted himself to the revealed

    preferences of individuals, which he registers as an independent observer (Reisman,

    1990, p. 154).

    Buchanan and Tullock made clear that the field of application of methodolog-

    ical individualism is much broader than significant action in a market economy

    (Lachman, 1969, p. 92). Schumpeter himself did not realize the scope of method-ological individualism, but nevertheless scholars still talk about the Schumpeter

    Research Programme (Boland, 1982, p. 28).

    Our conclusion has to be that, with methodological individualism, Schumpeter

    did introduce a new terminology, as Mark Blaug has written: The expression

    methodological individualism was apparently invented by Schumpeter as early as

    1908 (Blaug, 1980, p. 49). However, in no way did Schumpeter contribute to the

    development of its contents and the diffusion of its application within and outside

    economics.

  • 8/9/2019 Hertje_-_Schumpeter_and_methodological_individualism.pdf

    4/4

    156 A. Heertje

    References

    Blaug M (1980) The methodology of economics, or how economists explain. Cambridge University

    Press, Cambridge

    Boland LA (1982) The foundations of economic method. George Allen and Unwin, LondonBuchanan JM, Tullock G (1962) The calculus of consent, logical foundations of constitutional democ-

    racy. The University of Michigan Press, Ann Arbor, MI

    Buchanan JM (1975) The limits of liberty: between anarchy and Leviathan. The University of Chicago

    Press, Chicago

    Downs A (1957) An economic theory of democracy. Harper and Row, New York

    Lachman LM (1969) Methodological individualism and the market economy. In: Streissler E (ed) Roads

    to freedom. Essays in honour of F.A. Hayek. Routledge and Kegan, London

    Machlup F (1978) Methodology of economics and other social sciences. Academic Press, New York

    Menger C (1883) Untersuchungen uber die Methode der Sozialwissenschaften und der Politischen

    Oekonomie insbesondere. Duncker and Humblot, Leipzig

    Reisman D (1990) The political economy of James Buchanan. The Macmillan Press, LondonSchumpeter JA (1908) Das Wesen und der Hauptinhalt der theoretischen Nationalokonomie. Duncker

    and Humblot, Leipzig

    Schumpeter JA (1942) Capitalism, socialism and democracy. Harper and Brothers, New York

    Schumpeter JA (1954) History of economic analysis. George Allen and Unwin, Oxford

    Vaughn KI (1987) Carl Menger. In: The New Palgrave. The Macmillan Press, London