Jay Smith French Revolution Agency and Ideas

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

  • 7/23/2019 Jay Smith French Revolution Agency and Ideas

    1/28

    Wiley and Wesleyan Universityare collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to History and Theory.

    http://www.jstor.org

    Wesleyan University

    Between Discourse and Experience: Agency and Ideas in the French Pre-RevolutionAuthor(s): Jay M. SmithSource: History and Theory, Vol. 40, No. 4, Theme Issue 40: Agency after Postmodernism (Dec.,

    2001), pp. 116-142Published by: forWiley Wesleyan UniversityStable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/2677990Accessed: 29-04-2015 15:40 UTC

    EFEREN ESLinked references are available on JSTOR for this article:

    http://www.jstor.org/stable/2677990?seq=1&cid=pdf-reference#references_tab_contents

    You may need to log in to JSTOR to access the linked references.

    Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available athttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

    JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of contentin a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship.For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].

    This content downloaded from 130.63.180.147 on Wed, 29 Apr 2015 15:40:05 UTCAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=blackhttp://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=wesleyanhttp://www.jstor.org/stable/2677990http://www.jstor.org/stable/2677990?seq=1&cid=pdf-reference#references_tab_contentshttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/stable/2677990?seq=1&cid=pdf-reference#references_tab_contentshttp://www.jstor.org/stable/2677990http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=wesleyanhttp://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=blackhttp://www.jstor.org/
  • 7/23/2019 Jay Smith French Revolution Agency and Ideas

    2/28

  • 7/23/2019 Jay Smith French Revolution Agency and Ideas

    3/28

    BETWEENDISCOURSEAND EXPERIENCE

    117

    Inrecent years, many historiansof the FrenchRevolutionhave

    sought answers

    to these questions

    in

    the bedrock of experience. Reacting against

    both tradition-

    al social explanations, which showed motivations springing

    from seemingly

    objective

    class

    positions,

    and the revisionists'

    political/linguistic

    explanations,

    which often deduced

    agency

    from

    the logics internal

    o

    discourses, historiansof

    pre-Revolutionary nd RevolutionaryFrancehave begun to emphasize the deci-

    sive influenceof concrete

    experiences

    n

    the lives

    of

    individualsand

    groups.

    This

    new work is

    based

    on the

    commonsense assumption

    hat

    sensitive

    and

    thorough

    empirical analysis

    of the lived

    experiences

    of the

    past

    will

    enable historians of

    political

    action to

    navigate

    between the

    equally unappealingalternatives

    of

    old-

    fashioned

    social

    determinism,

    on

    the

    one

    hand,

    and

    newfangled

    linguistic

    deter-

    minism, on the other hand.2

    Contemplating

    he

    prospect

    of

    a

    post-revisionisthistory

    of

    eighteenth-century

    France, Vivian Grudercalled in 1997 for a new political history "closely cali-

    brated o the

    unfolding

    of

    events,

    the

    impact

    of concrete

    experience,"

    a

    form of

    analysis

    more sensitive to the

    ways

    in

    which

    "conceptspresent

    n

    discursive lan-

    guage

    .

    .

    . summed

    up

    and

    crystallized multiple prior

    experiences." Gruder

    described

    a movement

    alreadyunderway,

    or

    as

    Jack Censerobserved

    in a

    recent

    review

    article, many

    historiansof the

    Revolution are now attempting o leaven

    their

    analyses

    of

    "linguistic

    constructions"

    with

    an interest

    n

    "social

    conditions,"

    "lived

    experience,"

    and the

    weighing

    of "real ife

    opportunities."3 he examples

    are numerous. William H. Sewell's analysis of the Abbe Sieyes's What is the

    ThirdEstate? seeks to capture he text as both discursive artifactand as

    "action

    in a

    social

    world";

    Paul Hanson's work

    on monarchistpolitical

    clubs

    seeks to

    show that

    real

    events and actions "political experience, that

    is"-shaped the

    discourse

    of both Revolutionariesand

    counter-Revolutionaries;

    avid

    Andress's

    analysis

    of

    the

    Champs

    de Mars massacre

    concentrateson the

    political

    elite's

    misunderstanding

    f

    popular

    dissent

    and its

    failure to

    develop

    a

    vocabulary

    hat

    captured

    and

    responded

    o the unrest of

    1791.4

    Despite

    its renewed

    appeal

    to historians

    of

    eighteenth-century

    rance,

    howev-

    er,

    the

    concept

    of

    experience

    has

    been

    subjected

    to

    a critical

    scrutiny

    that

    seems

    2. Similarassumptionsobviously also lie behind the continuedattraction f

    "microhistory" nd the

    history

    of

    "everyday

    ife."

    See

    the

    insightful review article by

    Brad

    S. Gregory,

    "Is

    Small

    Beautiful?

    Microhistory

    and

    the History of Everyday Life," History and Theory38 (1999), 100-110. The

    essay

    discusses The

    History of EverydayLife: Reconstructing

    Historical

    Experiences

    and

    Waysof Life, ed.

    Alf Ludtke, transl. William Templer (Princeton: Princeton University Press,

    1995), and Jeux

    d'Echelles: La Micro-Analyseai 'Expirience, ed. JacquesRevel (Paris:Gallimard,1996).

    3. Vivian Gruder,"WhitherRevisionism? Political Perspectives on the Ancien

    R6gime," French

    Historical Studies 20 (1997), 254; Jack Censer, "Social Twists and Linguistic

    Turns:Revolutionary

    Historiography Decade after the Bicentennial,"French Historical Studies

    22

    (1999), 146.

    4.

    William H.

    Sewell, Jr.,

    A

    Rhetoric of Bourgeois Revolution:

    The

    Abbe

    Sieyes and What s the

    ThirdEstate? (Durham,N.C.: Duke University Press, 1994), 36; Paul R. Hanson,

    "Monarchist

    Clubs

    and the Pamphlet Debate over Political Legitimacy in the Early Years of the French Revolution,"

    French Historical Studies 21 (1998), 299-324, esp. 301; David Andress, "The Denial

    of Social

    Conflict in the French Revolution: Discourses around he

    Champ

    de Mars

    Massacre,

    17

    July 1791,"

    French Historical Studies

    22

    (1999), 183-209.

    This content downloaded from 130.63.180.147 on Wed, 29 Apr 2015 15:40:05 UTCAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/23/2019 Jay Smith French Revolution Agency and Ideas

    4/28

    118

    JAY M. SMITH

    only to intensify with

    the

    passing of years.5

    n

    the field of laborhistory,

    or

    exam-

    ple, E. P. Thompson'snotion of "working-class xperience,"which he saw as the

    crucible of workers' consciousness, spawned a complex

    and

    still

    smoldering

    debate aboutthe implicit dividing line separating xperience from consciousness

    in cultural histories of the working

    class.6

    Historians of gender and sexuality

    have similarly called into question the correlationbetween identityand the per-

    sonal experiences typically assumed to have produced t. Joan Scott,

    in a much-

    cited article, trenchantlyobserved that since individual subjectsnever occupy a

    neutralposition free of ideological constraintsand relations of power,

    the mean-

    ing of the experiences they construeand process is always dependent

    on the per-

    spectives, or subject positions,

    that

    they occupy.7 Meanwhile, post-structuralists

    and studentsof narrativehave drawn attention o the retrospectiveconstruction

    of

    experience,

    and the inclination of both individuals

    and

    groups

    to read

    their

    pasts as coherent storiesbuilt aroundmeaningful, ife-alteringevents.8

    This article responds

    not

    only to History and Theory'stimely

    call for essays

    examiningthe issue

    of

    agency

    in

    historical

    analysis,

    but also to currentsof dis-

    cussion now swirling

    about

    my

    own field of Old

    Regime

    and

    Revolutionary

    France. Like other dix-huitiemistes, ncluding many who celebrate the recent

    5. For acute discussions of historians'ambivalent

    relationship o the notion of experience since the

    linguistic turn, see BarryShank, "ConjuringEvidence for Experience:Imagining a Post-Structuralist

    History,"AmericanStudies 36 (1995), 81-92; MartinJay, "The Limits of Limit-Experience:Bataille

    and Foucault," WorkingPaper 3.11, European Society and CultureResearch Group, University of

    California at Berkeley (Berkeley, 1993); Miguel

    A. Cabrera, "Linguistic Approach

    or Return to

    Subjectivism?In Search of

    an Alternative

    to Social

    History,"Social History

    24

    (1999), 74-89; and

    Michael Pickering,History,Experience,

    and

    Cultural

    Studies (New York:St. Martin'sPress, 1997).

    6. The literaturedevoted to

    this

    aspect of Thompson's

    legacy is vast. For helpful reviews of the

    main points of debate, see

    Sean

    Scalmer, "Experience

    and Discourse: A

    Map

    of Recent Theoretical

    Approaches o Labourand

    Social

    History,"

    Labour History vol. no.? (1996), 156-168,

    and

    Marc W.

    Steinberg, "Culturally Speaking: Finding

    a Commons between Post-structuralism

    and

    the

    ThompsonianPerspective,"Social History

    21

    (1996), 193-214. Also see

    E. P.

    Thompson:Critical

    Perspectives,ed. HarveyJ. Kayeand Keith McClelland Oxford:Polity, 1990 ), andRethinkingLabor

    History: Essays on Discourseand Class Analysis,ed. LenardR. Berlanstein Urbana,

    ll.:

    University

    of Illinois Press, 1993).

    7. Joan W.

    Scott,

    "The

    Evidence

    of

    Experience,"

    Critical Inquiry

    17

    (1991), 773-797.

    See also

    Judith

    Butler, Gender

    Trouble:

    Feminism and the

    Subversion of Identity (New

    York:

    Routledge,

    1990); and Feminists Theorize

    the

    Political,

    ed. Judith Butler and Joan W. Scott (New York:

    Routledge, 1992). AlthoughI am sympathetic,andobviously indebted, o Scott's elegant and persua-

    sive

    argument,

    n "The Evidence

    of

    Experience,"against

    the foundationalism mplicit

    in the

    analysis

    of

    experience, her own emphasis

    on the constitutive power of discourse

    leaves little

    space for

    the

    exercise of individual

    agency.

    The

    present

    article builds on and

    supplements

    Scott's

    argument

    n

    its

    attempt to conceptualize the space between discourse and experience, the space where individuals

    weigh options and make moral

    choices.

    8.

    See,

    for

    example,

    Paul

    Ricoeur,

    Timeand

    Narrative,

    3

    vols.,

    transl.

    Kathleen

    McLaughlin

    and

    David Pellauer(Chicago: University

    of

    Chicago Press,

    1984-1988), esp.

    vol.

    3;

    idem,

    "Life in

    Quest

    of

    Narrative,"

    in On Paul

    Ricoeur: Narrative and

    Interpretation,

    ed. David Wood

    (London:

    Routledge, 1991); Douglas Ezzy,

    "Lived

    Experience

    and

    Interpretation

    n Narrative

    Theory:

    Experiences of Living

    with

    HIV/AIDS," Qualitative

    Sociology 21 (1998), 169-179; Mark Freeman,

    Rewriting

    the

    Self: History, Memory,

    Narrative

    (London:

    Routledge, 1993);

    see also Freeman'sdis-

    cussion of several

    different

    approaches

    in

    "Experience,Narrative,

    and

    the

    Relationship

    between

    Them,"Journal of Narrative

    and

    Life History 8 (1998),455-466;

    Donald Brenneis,"Telling

    Troubles:

    Narrative,Conflict and Experience,"AnthropologicalLinguistics30 (1988), 279-291.

    This content downloaded from 130.63.180.147 on Wed, 29 Apr 2015 15:40:05 UTCAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/23/2019 Jay Smith French Revolution Agency and Ideas

    5/28

    BETWEENDISCOURSEAND EXPERIENCE

    119

    "revivalof the social,"I yearn

    for a new mode of analysis that can

    account both

    for

    the

    powerful

    influence of

    linguistic

    structuresand for the

    drama

    of

    personal

    decision-making

    and

    sheer

    historicalcontingency.9

    But

    unlike the historianswho

    eagerly seek

    an

    antidote to the

    perceived excesses of postmodernism,

    I

    remain

    deeply skepticalof the analysis

    of experience, which, thanks

    n

    partto the recent

    groundswell of interest in solidly "social"phenomena, s now emergingas one

    of the primaryalternatives o

    discourse analysis in eighteenth-century

    tudies.10

    My

    doubts

    aboutthe concept

    of

    experience

    derive

    in

    part

    rom

    the same concerns

    that historiansof labor, gender,and narrativehave already articulated,

    but I am

    especially mistrustfulof the

    tendency

    to invoke

    experience

    as an

    explanation

    or

    purposeful political action,

    including

    revolution.

    I

    argue

    in

    this article that

    in

    order o understand

    ow

    subjective

    perceptions

    of the world

    get

    transformed

    nto

    political agency,

    historiansneed

    to

    resist

    the

    lure

    of

    the

    category

    of

    experience

    and adopt a new approachto the study of human consciousness, an approach

    designed

    to

    penetrate

    structuresof belief. Greater

    appreciation

    or the

    ways

    in

    which

    worlds

    are

    both sustainedand remade

    through

    beliefs

    will

    ultimatelyyield

    more satisfying explanations of how and why people act politically, and

    why

    they sometimes even come together

    to

    make a

    revolution.

    9. The phrase s from Censer, "Social Twists and Linguistic Turns,"161.

    10.

    The

    search for new alternatives o discourse analysis has also involved many historians and

    social scientists sympathetic o at least some aspects of postmodernism, ncluding some who are fully

    awareof the analyticaldeficiencies of the category of experience. Virtuallyall of the

    new alternatives

    they have articulated, owever, ultimatelyoppose language/culture o somethingostensibly more real,

    thus creatingnew interpretivedilemmas. See, for example, GarethStedmanJones's

    incisive critique

    of Roger Chartier'scategories of "representation" nd "practice," n "The Determinist

    Fix: Some

    Obstacles to the FurtherDevelopment of the Linguistic Approach o History in the

    1990s," History

    Workshop ournal

    42

    (1996), 19-35, esp.

    26-27. Stedman Jones

    developed

    further his line of criti-

    cism

    in

    his

    review

    of

    Les

    Formes de l'experience:

    une

    autre

    histoire

    sociale, ed.

    BernardLepetit

    (Paris:

    A.

    Michel, 1995).

    See Stedman

    Jones,

    "Une autre

    histoire

    sociale?,"

    Annales: Histoire,

    Sciences Sociales

    53

    (1998), 383-392.

    RichardBiernacki's

    attempt

    o

    distinguish

    between "signs"

    and

    "practice" aises problems similar to those criticized by Stedman Jones. See Biernacki,"Language

    andthe Shift from Signs to Practicesin CulturalHistory,"Historyand Theory 39 (2000), 289-3 10,

    and

    the

    critical

    commentaryby Chris Lorenz

    in the same

    volume, "Some

    Afterthoughtson Culture

    and Explanation n HistoricalInquiry,"History and Theory39 (2000), 348-363, esp. 359. The danger

    in

    tryingto

    find

    new ways to bridge

    the

    supposedgap between

    lived

    "reality"

    nd its interpretation r

    representation

    s that the effort

    inevitably perpetuatesunhelpful polarities

    that divert attentionfrom

    the central

    problem

    of consciousness. Kathleen

    Canning,

    for

    example,

    tries to

    get

    at the

    culturally

    conditioned

    agency

    of

    working-class

    women

    by focusing

    on

    the

    body,

    "in both its discursive and

    experiential

    dimensions"

    (Canning,

    "Feminist

    History

    after the

    Linguistic

    Turn:

    Historicizing

    Dis-

    course and

    Experience,"Signs

    19

    [1994], 368-404, esp. 386).

    William

    H.

    Sewell,

    Jr. has

    suggested

    thatanalysisof social changemust incorporateboth "semioticexplanation"and"mechanicalexpla-

    nation"

    that

    supposes

    the

    operation

    of non-semiotic

    logics ("demographic,

    echnological, coercive,

    institutional,

    and

    the like"); see Sewell, "Language

    and

    Practice

    n

    CulturalHistory:

    Backing Away

    from the

    Edge

    of the

    Cliff,"

    French Historical

    Studies

    21

    (1998), 241-254, esp.

    252. GabrielleSpiegel

    has

    similarly called for greaterattention o

    the

    "social logic of the text,"

    as distinctfromits semiotic

    logic ("History,Historicism,

    and

    the Social Logic

    of the Text

    in

    the

    Middle Ages," Speculum

    65

    [1990], 59-86).

    These newer and subtler

    oppositions

    between

    basic

    realities

    and

    imaginative

    con-

    structions,

    for all their

    ingenuity,

    still

    manage

    to cut short the

    analysis

    of

    consciousness

    and

    the

    process

    of

    interpretation.

    n each of these

    formulations,

    he historian

    s

    spared

    the trouble

    of

    pene-

    trating

    he

    labyrinth

    of the mind

    because the productionof consciousness

    is tracedback to phenome-

    na

    that supposedly possess self-evident causative implications.

    This content downloaded from 130.63.180.147 on Wed, 29 Apr 2015 15:40:05 UTCAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/23/2019 Jay Smith French Revolution Agency and Ideas

    6/28

    120

    JAY M.

    SMITH

    To clarify what

    is

    it at stake

    in

    historians'use of experienceas an analyticalcat-

    egory,

    the

    article begins

    with a

    necessarily detailed

    discussion of Timothy

    Tackett's approach to the concept in his

    influential book, Becoming a

    Revolutionary."

    Because of the force and clarity

    of

    the

    argumenthe pursues,

    Tackett'sanalysis of the developing conflicts between

    deputies to the National

    Assembly in 1789-1790 can be used to exemplify theexperiential urn hatmarks

    much recentwork on the eighteenthcentury.After

    identifying

    he

    problems nher-

    ent

    in

    this new

    orientation

    toward

    experience, the

    article offers an

    alternative

    approach o the study of political consciousness,

    an

    interpretation

    erived from

    a

    close readingof the words, and mind, of

    a

    single participant

    n

    the

    revolutionary

    drama, he lawyer Joseph-Michel-AntoineServan

    (1737-1807).

    I.

    EXPERIENCEAS A

    SOURCE

    OF IDEAS:

    THE EXAMPLE OF

    BECOMING

    A

    REVOLUTIONARY

    The ensuing discussion requires a preliminary

    disclaimer.Although

    I

    focus on

    what

    I

    consider to be an imperfectionof Becoming a

    Revolutionary,my purpose

    is not to

    challenge the book's status

    as a landmark

    work. Becoming a Revolu-

    tionarystands

    as

    a monument o careful research,and it

    performed he overdue

    task of

    putting people-rather than ideas, discourses,and cultures-back at the

    center of FrenchRevolutionary tudies. More

    specifically,Tackett'sbook provid-

    ed a

    powerful empiricalchallenge

    to the

    common

    claim that

    nobles

    and

    wealthy

    members of the thirdestate

    formed

    a

    large

    and

    homogeneous elite

    on the

    eve

    of

    the Revolution. He

    demonstrated, hroughanalysis

    of

    incomes and careers,

    and

    through the barbed comments of the deputies themselves, that differences

    in

    materialconditionsand cultural

    perspectiveseparated

    he

    greatmajority

    of noble

    representatives

    rom

    the

    great majority

    of those

    representing

    he third estate.

    At

    the same

    time,

    he showed that

    the

    social

    animositiesdividing the thirdestate from

    the

    privileged

    orderswere laced with

    uncertainty

    nd

    ambiguity.

    For both of these

    reasons-his

    helpful

    reassessmentof the

    pre-Revolutionary

    milieu the

    deputies

    inhabited,

    and his

    emphasis on the unpredictability of the Revolutionary

    moment-Tackett's evidence has added fuel to the

    many post-revisionistargu-

    ments

    being developed by

    others

    in

    the

    field, including

    my

    own.12

    Becoming

    a

    Revolutionary

    has

    been unanimouslypraised by

    reviewers,

    it

    received

    a

    presti-

    gious prize

    from the

    AHA,

    and it

    unquestionablydeserves

    its

    wide acclaim."3

    11. TimothyTackett,Becominga Revolutionary:TheDeputies of the FrenchNationalAssemblyand

    the Emergenceof a RevolutionaryCulture 1789-1 790) (Princeton:PrincetonUniversityPress, 1996).

    12. See, for example, Jay M. Smith, "Social Categories, the Language of Patriotism, and the

    Origins of the French Revolution: The Debate over Noblesse

    Commerqante,"

    ournal of Modern

    History 72 (2000), 339-374,

    and

    "Recovering Tocqueville's Social Interpretationof the French

    Revolution:Eighteenth-Century ranceRethinksNobility," n Beyond Tocqueville:New Perspectives

    on the Ancien

    Regime,

    ed.

    Robert Schwartz

    and

    Robert Schneider (Newark:University of Delaware

    Press, 2002).

    both

    of

    which

    present argumentsperfectly

    consistent with Tackett's

    indings.

    13. The

    book

    received

    the Leo Gershoy Award n 1997 as the best book

    in

    early-modemwestern

    Europeanhistory publishedin 1996. Among the many glowing reviews see, for example, those by

    Gwynne Lewis, Times Literary Supplement (February28, 1997), 30; William Doyle, Journal of

    Modern History 69 (1997), 852; Alan B. Spitzer, Annals of the AmericanAcademyof Political and

    Social

    Science 566

    (1999), 172;

    and Sarah

    Maza,

    Journal

    of InterdisciplinaryHistory

    28

    (1997),

    112.

    This content downloaded from 130.63.180.147 on Wed, 29 Apr 2015 15:40:05 UTCAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/23/2019 Jay Smith French Revolution Agency and Ideas

    7/28

    BETWEENDISCOURSEAND EXPERIENCE 121

    One aspect of the book that requires close critical attention,however, is its

    treatmentof the relationshipbetween consciousness and agency. In his introduc-

    tion Tackett announced his frustrationwith the stale debate over whether the

    Revolution had

    had

    "social" or "political" origins. The

    time had

    come, he

    declared,to leave aside burdensomehistoriographical gendas and "to focus ...

    on the Revolutionaryexperienceof the specific individualswho took part n and

    embodied [the] Revolution. How did men and women become

    Revolutionaries?"14 ackett explained that, because the book focused on the

    rapidlychangingmentalityof the hundredsof deputieswhoreported o Versailles

    in

    May, 1789, only to find themselves remaking he nation

    a

    few weeks later,

    his

    was essentially

    a

    study

    in collective

    psychology.

    It follows, insofar as possible, the transformation f the deputies' values and mode

    of

    thinking, . . .

    In

    so doing, however,

    it makes the

    assumption

    hat culture s

    'produced'not

    only through ntellectualexperience,but throughsocial andpolitical experienceas well,

    and that it is impossible to understandhow individuals 'read' their world without

    a

    full

    delineationof the contours

    of

    theirlives.15

    In otherwords, Tackettaimed to provide a balancedand measuredaccountof the

    actual revolutionaryexperience,

    an account that

    would show why

    the

    revolu-

    tionaries

    behaved as

    they

    did

    in

    the heat

    of

    the initial battles of the Revolution.

    To many specialists, the tone of Tackett'sprose, and his evidently reasonable

    objectives,

    came as a

    welcome change.

    In

    contrastto

    much

    of the work of the

    1980s and early 1990s, which focused on semiotic systems, ideological con-

    structions,

    and

    the

    many

    dimensions of

    representation,

    Tackett's

    analysis

    seemed

    to rest on

    straightforward

    vidence

    and

    refreshing

    common

    sense.

    The initial

    positive impression

    s

    continually

    reinforced

    by

    the

    author's

    becoming

    intellec-

    tual

    modesty

    and

    the

    painstaking

    esearch

    hat

    undergirds

    his account.

    The

    atten-

    tive

    reader soon detects, however,

    that

    even

    Tackett's

    empirically grounded

    argument

    s

    rooted

    in a

    set of theoretical

    suppositions.By probing

    those

    suppo-

    sitions, especially as revealedin Tackett'sanalysisof the developing animosity

    between noble

    and

    common

    deputies

    in

    the

    spring

    and summerof

    1789,

    I

    hope

    to

    demonstrate that

    his

    method

    of

    connecting experience

    to action

    actually

    obscures the

    fundamental

    ognitive processes

    that lie behind

    political

    choice.

    The basis for Tackett's

    working assumptions

    about the nature of

    political

    process

    can be found in his

    repudiation

    of

    discourse

    analysis

    and

    the

    fully

    devel-

    oped

    revisionism

    of

    the

    1980s.

    In

    opposition

    to the now familiar

    argument,

    advanced

    by

    Frangois

    Furet and

    others,

    that the

    reign

    of Terror

    developed logi-

    cally andineluctablyout of the Rousseauianrhetoricof the general will, Tackett

    maintained hat the course of

    Revolutionaryevents,

    and the

    mentality

    that

    made

    those events

    possible, grew

    out

    of

    political contingencies specific

    to the time.

    Surveying

    the attitudesand

    early writings

    of the

    third-estate

    deputies

    who would

    later embrace

    Revolutionary deals,

    Tackettobserved that

    although"virtually

    all

    were familiar with some elements of the

    Enlightenment,

    ..

    little evidence

    can

    14. Tackett,Becoming, 7.

    15. Ibid., 13.

    This content downloaded from 130.63.180.147 on Wed, 29 Apr 2015 15:40:05 UTCAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/23/2019 Jay Smith French Revolution Agency and Ideas

    8/28

    122

    JAY M. SMITH

    be found before the Revolution of an oppositional ideology or 'discourse"';by

    and

    large they

    were

    practical

    men

    who

    read

    law, history,

    and

    science,

    and

    had no

    inclination toward "abstractphilosophy."16On the eve of the Revolution their

    political

    culture "was

    shaped less by books

    and

    essays

    than

    by

    their

    concrete

    political

    and

    social

    experience

    under the Old

    Regime."

    7

    They

    went on to make

    their ideological choices in light of "specific political contingencies and social

    interactionswithin the Assembly and between the Assembly and the population

    as a

    whole."18

    But

    how

    did these

    various "concrete"

    and

    "contingent"phenom-

    ena

    actually

    affect the

    thinking

    of the

    deputies?

    Tackettaddresses that

    question

    by outlining

    a

    two-stage process of coming-to-consciousness, a process that

    looks plausible only

    if

    one accepts the propositionthat experience happens out-

    side the mind and carries

    nherentlyrecognizablemeanings.

    Tackettunderstandably ees the Revolution as

    a

    transformative vent,

    a

    radi-

    cal break with what came before, but because of the analyticaltraditionagainst

    which he is reacting-what Gruderhas called "the argumentof discourse"-he

    is anxious to establish that the events of the Revolution were not inscribedwith-

    in the

    political debates of

    the

    Old Regime.19Few of the future members of the

    Constituent

    Assembly,

    he

    writes,

    "had

    anticipated

    he transformations hat were

    about

    to

    take

    place"

    when

    they convened

    at

    Versailles

    in

    May, 1789. "For the

    great majority,

    t

    was only after May 5,

    in

    the extraordinarily reative process of

    the Assembly itself, that a 'Revolution of the Mind' came about."20 his argu-

    ment comes perilously close to tautology-the revolutionariesare made revolu-

    tionaryby

    the

    revolution

    that

    they themselves

    are

    making-but

    Tackett

    narrow-

    ly avoids the tautologicaltrapby evoking two

    differentkinds

    of experience, one

    corresponding

    o what

    might

    be called social

    formation,

    he other to immediate

    sensory perception.21

    The

    key

    to the

    process

    of causation

    in

    Tackett's

    analysis

    lies

    in

    the

    convergence

    of these two forms of

    experience,

    which become mutual-

    ly reinforcing

    and thus

    culturallyproductive.

    As one would expect, the formativeaspects of experience occupy

    Tackett's

    attention

    n

    the

    chapters

    devoted to

    pre-Revolutionary

    France.

    Judging

    from a

    whole

    range

    of

    objective measures,

    the social

    backgrounds

    of the

    deputies rep-

    resenting

    the third estate differed

    markedly

    from

    the

    social

    background

    of

    the

    privileged orders,

    and

    especially

    that of the

    nobility.

    Tackett

    begins

    the book

    by

    filling

    out the social

    profiles

    of the noble

    and

    commoner

    deputies-incomes,

    careers,dowries,

    educational

    evels, status,

    nstitutional

    affiliationsand he

    goes

    16. Ibid., 14.

    17. Ibid., 305.

    18. Ibid., 76.

    19. Gruder,"WhitherRevisionism?,"247.

    20. Tackett,Becoming, 307.

    21. Tackett'sbifurcated reatmentof experience is strikingly similar to Wilhem Dilthey's analyti-

    cal distinctionbetween Erlebnis (which

    can

    be translated oughly

    as

    "immediate ensory experience")

    and Erfahrung ("knowledge gained from lived experience"), though Tackett makes no allusion to

    Dilthey. For

    discussion

    of Dilthey's categories

    see

    Pickering,History,Experience,94-124;

    Martin

    Jay,

    "Experience without a Subject: Walter Benjamin and the Novel," New Formations:

    A

    Journal of

    Culture/Theory/Politics0 (1993), 145-155; andJay,"The Limitsof Limit-Experience," -6.

    This content downloaded from 130.63.180.147 on Wed, 29 Apr 2015 15:40:05 UTCAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/23/2019 Jay Smith French Revolution Agency and Ideas

    9/28

    BETWEENDISCOURSEAND EXPERIENCE

    123

    on to assert that the respective social worlds establishedby those objective para-

    meters instilled in the deputies distinctive

    values and habits of thought. After

    assessing the backgroundsof the

    noble deputies, for example, Tackett places

    emphasis on their nearly universal

    attachment o the military.

    Even

    if

    a minorityof deputies

    had

    revolted

    against militaryvalues, the

    critical formative

    years spentin the armedforces, from the mid-teensto the early twenties, invariablyhad

    an

    impact.Training

    n

    swordplay

    and horsemanship,

    n

    militarydiscipline,

    in

    the ideals

    of

    honor,

    hierarchical

    ommand,

    and devotion to the king,

    all

    left a stamp that would clear-

    ly distinguish

    he

    corps

    of

    the Second Estate

    from their colleagues in the Commons.It was

    an influencethatwould stronglyaffect many membersof the Nobility

    in

    their fundamen-

    tal

    assumptions

    aboutthe nature

    of

    society and

    social

    relationshipsdespite

    the common

    veneer of eighteenth-century urban culture which touched both Nobles

    and

    Commoners.22

    Tackettsees proofof this instinctive attachment o the values instilledby experi-

    ence

    in the

    political positions

    later articulated

    by

    noble

    deputies,

    which

    reflect-

    ed,

    he

    says,

    their

    "underlyingpolitical

    cultureand

    the

    military-aristocratic

    thos

    which informedthat culture."23

    The deputiesof the thirdestate looked

    less socially homogeneousthanthe

    rep-

    resentatives of the nobility, but Tackett argues that they, too, had come from

    a

    distinctive milieu that shapedtheirthinking

    n

    subtle ways. More

    than half came

    from the legal profession,

    and at least two-thirds"had

    probably

    received training

    in the law."24Most were respectableproperty owners, and "a substantialand

    influentialsegment of the deputieshad acquiredpractice

    in

    collective politics

    at

    the

    town, provincial,

    and even

    national

    levels."25For the most

    part

    these were

    deliberate,practical, responsible

    men whose

    writings

    "alludedmore

    frequently

    to

    history

    and the

    classics,

    than to

    reason

    and the

    general

    will

    or to Rousseau

    and

    Voltaire."

    In

    fact, they

    later evinced little

    interest in

    the

    various strands of

    Enlightenmentdiscourse,

    which seemed irrelevant to

    the "concrete

    problems

    facing

    them

    in

    the

    Assembly."26

    At

    the outset of the

    Revolution,

    the

    deputies

    of

    the thirdestate were conciliatoryandconservative-minded eformers,not angry

    firebrands.

    Tackett uggests, however,

    that

    n

    some

    respects

    the

    experience

    of

    living

    under

    the

    Old Regime

    had

    prepared

    he

    deputies

    of the third

    estate,

    at

    some

    vaguely

    subconscious

    level,

    to

    pursue

    radical social transformation

    when the

    opportuni-

    ty arose.

    Because

    they possessed

    a

    less exalted status

    than most

    members

    of the

    nobility

    in the

    pre-Revolutionary

    social

    hierarchy,

    and

    because

    their

    wealth,

    though

    often

    considerable,placed

    them well below the level of material

    splendor

    enjoyed by great aristocrats,

    Tackett

    nfers

    that their lives involved "a

    potential

    for frustration

    nd

    tension."Ambitious

    n

    their

    careers,

    and

    often desirousof

    pos-

    sessing

    noble status for themselves

    or their

    progeny, many

    future

    deputies

    con-

    22. Tackett,Becoming, 34-35.

    23. Ibid., 136. Italics

    added.

    24. Ibid., 36.

    25. Ibid., 100.

    26. Ibid., 65.

    This content downloaded from 130.63.180.147 on Wed, 29 Apr 2015 15:40:05 UTCAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/23/2019 Jay Smith French Revolution Agency and Ideas

    10/28

    124

    JAY M. SMITH

    fronted n their daily routines the irreduciblesocial differences separating hem

    from the establishednobility.Tackettassumes that awarenessof these differences

    must have fostered discontent. "For some individualdeputies [their] ambiguous

    social

    standing

    had

    undoubtedlyengendered

    a

    sense of humiliation and anger

    thatremainedclose to the surface."27 "deep-seated"

    nti-aristocratic

    itterness,

    ''engendered y the social and legal systemin which they lived," would affect the

    political posture

    of

    representatives

    of the thirdestate

    in

    ways

    that most of them

    did not anticipate.Feelings of jealousy, injustice, and bitternesswere "present n

    the hearts"of many deputies of the thirdestate when they convened at Versailles

    in

    May, 1789, and this bitterness "was to be a central element . . . in the emer-

    gence

    of a

    revolutionary

    consciousness

    within

    that Estate at the

    beginning

    of

    June 1789."28Although Tackett inds little evidence of revolutionaryconscious-

    ness preceding the Revolution, a revolutionary consciousness sprang readily

    fromthe frustratedminds of the thirdestate once political confrontationprovid-

    ed the necessary provocation.

    The experiences associatedwith theirrespective social formationshad impart-

    ed to the

    deputies

    of the second and thirdestates certain

    underlyingattitudes

    a

    commitment o honor

    and

    status for the

    nobles,

    largely unarticulated esentment

    for the commoners. But

    in

    Tackett's

    narrative, these attitudes hardened into

    uncompromisingpolitical agendas only

    after the

    deputies endured

    anotherkind

    of

    experience

    in the

    spring

    and

    summer of 1789, namely, the protracteddebate

    over

    voting procedures

    n the

    assembly.

    Since the last weeks of

    1788,

    liberals

    from all the ordershad been arguingfor a symbolic mergerof the three

    estates,

    common deliberations

    n

    the

    assembly,

    and

    voting by

    head rather han

    by order.

    All

    of these key procedural ssues had been left unresolved by the king, and

    many deputies

    had

    hoped to reach

    a

    workable compromise

    at

    the opening ses-

    sions of the Estates-General.

    Tackett

    emphasizes

    that the

    deputies

    of the third

    estate, despite

    their

    high

    hopes, found themselves confrontinga "cultureof intransigence"on the partof

    thenobility.29 ProvincialandParisian, itled anduntitled,robe

    and

    sword, young

    and

    old,

    the

    great majority

    of all Nobles were

    aggressively

    hostile to

    the liberals

    [of

    the Second

    Estate]

    and

    the

    position they represented."30

    he

    political

    choic-

    es of the noble

    deputies,

    Tackett

    writes,

    "were determined ess

    by

    inter-estate

    rivalries than

    by

    the

    ideological positions

    and culturalvalues shared

    by

    a

    great

    many

    nobles at all levels

    in

    society.'"31

    he

    majority

    remained

    "deeply

    convinced

    of their

    innate

    superiority."They

    were

    "stronglypenetrated

    with a

    military,

    even

    feudal sense of honor and duty."One even finds them referring"to models of

    noble

    courage

    and

    chivalry

    from the

    past,"

    and

    using

    a "chivalric

    vocabulary

    of

    defending

    one's honor and

    proving

    one's

    loyalty

    to the

    king."32

    Offended

    by

    the

    27. Ibid., 46.

    28. Ibid., 109-110.

    29. Ibid., 132.

    30. Ibid.,

    134.

    31. Ibid., 133.

    32. Ibid., 136-137.

    This content downloaded from 130.63.180.147 on Wed, 29 Apr 2015 15:40:05 UTCAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/23/2019 Jay Smith French Revolution Agency and Ideas

    11/28

    BETWEENDISCOURSEAND EXPERIENCE

    125

    constitutionalclaims of the third estate,

    and rallied by conservative

    spokesmen

    such as D'Antraigues

    and

    Cazales,

    the great majority of the deputies of the

    Second Estate stubbornly

    defended the

    prerogativesof their order and rejected

    what they regarded

    as unconstitutionalprocedural nnovations.

    The deputies of

    the third estate, accordingto Tackett, elt

    frustrationand out-

    rage in the face of the nobles' inflexibility.For some, the nobility's unexpected

    obstinacy ed to a "wrenching xperience,

    entailing

    an

    agonizing

    re-evaluationof

    a value

    system

    to

    which

    they had long

    acquiesced."For others,noble stubborn-

    ness "aroused ong-held

    sentimentsof

    animosity and resentment, eelings which

    most had labored

    to suppress in the name of unity, in the pious

    hope that they

    might now be regardedas equals."Tackett

    contends that the

    deputies' frustrated

    hopes released "a deep-seated revulsion

    for the years of

    condescension and

    scorn"

    and

    produced

    an

    "all-consumingpassion" to

    win

    recognition

    of the third

    estate's

    rights.33

    n the first

    weeks

    of

    June, following

    a month of fruitless

    nego-

    tiations carried out by committees of

    the

    three

    orders,

    the third estate moved

    rapidly to constituteitself as the nation's

    true representative

    assembly. By the

    morningof June17,

    the

    deputies

    of the thirdestate had voted

    overwhelmingly o

    adopt the name

    "National

    Assembly"

    and to assume sovereign powers once

    reservedfor the

    king. For Tackett, hese first two and a half

    weeks

    in

    June repre-

    sent

    a

    "dramatic

    ransformation"

    n thinking,a revolutionarymoment

    "bornof

    a

    complex convergence

    of

    factors,

    some long developing

    androoted

    in

    the social

    and

    culturalstructures

    of

    the

    Old Regime

    and their consequenteffects on noble-

    commonerrelations,

    some relatedto the contingent

    ack

    of

    leadership

    and to

    the

    deputies'

    immediate

    experience

    in the Estates-General nd the actions

    and reac-

    tions of ThirdEstate

    and

    Nobility"

    in the weeks afterthe opening

    session of May

    5.34The converginglessons of experience

    ultimatelyproduced

    an awareness of

    irreconcilabledifferencesand set the

    thirdestate on an unanticipated

    evolution-

    ary

    course.

    For Tackett,then, the Revolution,and the antagonismsthat set it in motion,

    should be

    seen not as

    a

    discursive

    event,

    but as an event born of

    experience-

    both the

    long-term

    "social"

    experience

    of

    status, wealth,

    and career that

    had

    shaped

    he

    lives

    of

    the

    deputies,

    and

    the immediate

    "political"

    xperience

    of con-

    frontation

    n

    1789.

    For the

    nobles,

    their time

    in

    the schools

    and

    camps

    of the

    mil-

    itaryhad left

    a

    "stamp,"

    made

    an

    "impact,"

    xercised

    an

    "influence"

    hat,

    Tackett

    believes,

    established

    for

    them a kind of default

    ideology,

    a

    latent counter-revo-

    lutionary

    consciousness,

    that the

    political

    claims of

    the thirdestate

    in

    1788-1789

    inevitablyactivated.At the sametime,the thirdestate'sposturetoward he noble

    deputies

    in

    late

    May

    and

    early

    June

    reflected not

    so much "an intellectual

    posi-

    tion" but

    "an instinctive and

    visceral

    antipathy"brought

    to the

    surface

    by

    the

    deliberative

    process

    itself,

    which served to

    "crystallize

    and

    intensify

    social

    antagonisms,making many deputies

    far

    more

    self-conscious

    of those

    antago-

    nisms than ever before."35

    The

    revolutionary

    consciousness

    developed by

    the

    33. Ibid.,

    144.

    34. Ibid., 145, 147-148.

    35. Ibid., 308.

    This content downloaded from 130.63.180.147 on Wed, 29 Apr 2015 15:40:05 UTCAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/23/2019 Jay Smith French Revolution Agency and Ideas

    12/28

    126

    JAY M. SMITH

    third estate was a direct expression of immediate experience, a consciousness

    reinforcedby half-suppressedmemories of earlierantipathies.

    Historiansof eighteenth-century rancenow agree thatthe phenomenaTackett

    seeks to capture through his focus on experience, such as vocational training,

    material comfort, status anxieties, and the give and take of political debate,

    deservemoreattention hanthey receivedin revisionist analysisafterthe 1970s.

    Unfortunately, hough, Tackett'scommitment o experience as a discrete analyt-

    ical

    category-a category comprising "concrete"matter

    that stands

    apart

    from

    discourses, ideologies, and ideas-drives

    him

    inevitably toward

    a

    dubious

    defi-

    nition of consciousness. For Tackett,the function of consciousness is to record,

    and eventually to distill, the meanings of experience. While merely recording

    experience

    that

    is,

    when the mind is

    assimilating

    more or less

    unreflectively

    he

    externalrealities that

    shape

    it-

    consciousness

    is

    partly suppressed

    and

    manifests

    itself primarilyn culture.When actually distilling experience-that is, when the

    mind

    finally engages and pronouncesthe meanings derived from those external

    realities-consciousness rises to the surface and leads to action.

    Tackettcertainlyacknowledges the role of ideas in the development of a rev-

    olutionary consciousness, especially after the deputies passed the point of no

    return n

    June 1789.36But by emphasizingthe decisiveness of the experience of

    political conflict,

    he

    necessarily overlooks the intricate

    nterior

    process by

    which

    the

    deputies workedthrough heir ideas and values, thus enablingthem to assim-

    ilate the events of 1789, as well as earlier developments, to an evolving but

    coherent

    picture of

    the

    world.

    As

    Michael Oakeshottshrewdly observed,

    in his

    classic work on

    experience

    and

    perception, experiences, whetherthey

    take the

    shape

    of

    encounters, events, developments, or routines,

    do

    not present

    them-

    selves to the

    apprehending

    mind in

    splendid solation, announcing

    heir

    own

    sig-

    nificance

    and

    performing he work of the decipheringeye. Experiences acquire

    their

    meaning,

    and

    register

    heir

    existence, only through

    heir

    ncorporation

    with-

    in a

    largerworld of related meanings,

    a

    world whose tenuous coherence

    and

    unity depends

    on the active

    thinking

    of

    the

    interpreting gent.37

    When

    people

    sort

    through

    the individual strandsof

    word, deed,

    and encounterthat constitute the

    fabric of their

    lives, they

    confront these

    phenomena

    not

    as

    "concrete"materials

    that

    render

    judgment unnecessary,

    but

    as half-formed

    impressions

    that

    emerge

    over the

    conceptual horizon,

    dim

    silhouettes that

    achieve

    their

    definition

    only

    through

    the

    process

    of

    filtering

    and

    ordering

    that

    necessarily

    characterizes

    all

    thought.

    The

    key

    to

    uncovering the

    connection between

    consciousness

    and

    agency lies not in the analysisof experience per se, but in the processesof inter-

    36. Tackett's econd chapterprovides

    a

    survey of the various ntellectual

    nfluencesthathad helped

    to shape the deputies' attitudesat the outset of the Revolution. But he suggests

    that the very "com-

    plexity and ambiguity of their outlook" prevented hem from being disposed in

    any particulardirec-

    tion before the Revolution began. Only

    after

    the

    events

    of spring

    and summer1789, he observes,did

    referencesto

    the

    philosopher begin to appear

    n the

    writings of

    the

    deputies (63-64).

    37. Michael Oakeshott, Experience and its Modes [1933] (Cambridge:Cambridge

    University

    Press, 1966). "Judgment

    and

    experience are inseparable;wherever there

    is

    judgment

    there is infer-

    ence,

    and

    immediacyhas given place to mediation.

    And

    the

    claim

    of sensation to be, on account of

    its immediacy,

    a

    form of experience

    exclusive

    of thought,

    must be said to have failed" (17).

    This content downloaded from 130.63.180.147 on Wed, 29 Apr 2015 15:40:05 UTCAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/23/2019 Jay Smith French Revolution Agency and Ideas

    13/28

    BETWEENDISCOURSEAND EXPERIENCE 127

    pretation that inevitably intersect the phenomena one regards

    as the subject's

    experience.38To go where the action is, and to find the motors

    that drive histor-

    ical change, the historianneeds to dissect the interpretivedispositionsthat deter-

    mine how people engage, process, and learn from all that occurs

    in their lives.

    The analytical instinct to derive thought from forces external

    to the subject,

    such as discourse or experience, succeeds only in masking the creativity and

    moral determination hat characterize he active human consciousness.

    Tackett,

    for example, assumes that because the deputies had apparently

    not undergonea

    previous "Revolutionof the Mind" that could be attributed o

    a particular deol-

    ogy,

    "discourse" s ruled out as

    an

    explanation

    for their actions, leaving

    "social

    and

    political experience"as

    the likeliest source

    for

    the third estate's impatience

    in

    1789.

    But this

    either-orchoice,

    which focuses one's attentionoutside the

    mind

    of the subject, is misconceived. Interpretivedispositions are composed not of

    discourses, butof constellations of beliefs, ideas, and values that are often frag-

    mented, disconnected, composite, and even contradictory.

    Unlike discourses,

    which are defined by their structuralunity and which take shape

    only when an

    outside observer abstracts hem from the

    processes

    of

    cognition

    and

    communi-

    cation and reifies them

    for

    analytical purposes, interpretivedispositions

    are as

    untidy

    and

    unfixed

    as

    any

    human

    interaction,despite

    the structures

    hat

    frame

    them.

    They

    are

    inherently dynamic

    and

    susceptible

    to

    change

    because

    they

    reflect the multiple convictions

    and commitments on which the subject bases

    his/hersense of self, as well as the disparatebeliefs andassumptions hat inform

    those commitments.

    People

    exercise

    agency during every

    "event"

    or

    "experi-

    ence," including

    the

    fleeting

    and the random

    as well as

    the dramatic

    and the

    enduring,

    because their

    interpretivedispositions

    shift to meet

    every contingency.

    They

    refine their inclinations as

    their

    beliefs interact

    with

    the

    divergent

    and

    unsettlingpotentialities

    of their

    world, creating

    a desire for moral coherence

    and

    the search for

    a

    new center

    of

    gravity

    in the

    layers

    of their consciousness. This

    inescapably cognitive process reflects

    neither the instrumentaluse

    of

    putative

    "discourses"

    nor

    the

    "instinctiveand visceral" reactions to

    supposedly

    unmedi-

    ated

    experiences,

    but the

    subject's

    creative

    and

    ongoing

    reformulation

    f values

    andpriorities.

    The revolutionaryargumentsof 1789 reflected

    not a

    suddenpolitical

    awaken-

    ing

    but the

    final,

    and

    momentous, rearrangement

    f

    conceptual

    resources long

    familiar o both

    the

    deputies

    to the Estates-General

    nd theirconstituents.Tackett

    38. Cf. Stanley

    Fish's useful

    concept

    of

    "interpretive ommunities,"

    as

    developed

    in

    Is There

    a

    Text

    in this Class? (Cambridge,Mass.:

    HarvardUniversityPress, 1980).

    Fish's critics are right thathe goes

    too

    far

    in declaring that

    texts

    do not

    exist

    "prior o interpretation."

    ish's interpreting ubject pos-

    sesses a conceptual grid so coherent and self-replicating hat it resists

    all

    challenges

    to its organiza-

    tional principles, and therefore

    has

    no

    real

    need for contact

    with a

    world outside

    itself. But the more

    limited claim that emerges out of

    Fish's discussion, namely, that interpretiveassumptionsare always

    inescapable,both for groups and forthe individualswho comprise them, seems

    incontrovertible.For

    critical discussion of Fish's concept of interpretive ommunities, see Gerald

    Graff, "Interpretationn

    Tlhn: A Response to Stanley Fish,"

    New Literary

    History

    17 (1985), 109-117,

    followed by a reply

    from Fish, "Resistance and Independence:

    A Reply to Gerald Graff," 119-127.

    See also Robert

    Scholes, Textual

    Power

    (New

    Haven:Yale University Press, 1985).

    This content downloaded from 130.63.180.147 on Wed, 29 Apr 2015 15:40:05 UTCAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/23/2019 Jay Smith French Revolution Agency and Ideas

    14/28

    128

    JAY M. SMITH

    represents he attitudesof the deputies on the eve of the Revolution as a product

    of the OldRegime's"socialand legal system," a naturaloutgrowthof the "social

    and

    cultural structures"of the age. For Tackett, the common deputies' angry

    response to the nobility's defense of its prerogativeswas a sign of their resent-

    ment againstthe "condescensionand scorn" hathad characterized heirrelations

    with the Second Estate for many years.39But can the "system"or "structure" f

    the

    Old Regime really be creditedwith bestowing on futuredeputies of the third

    estate

    the "pious hope" that they would soon be regardedas the equals of the

    nobility? How so? Systems and structures,no matterhow hierarchical,are never

    inherentlyunfair,and experience of them thereforecannot simply be expected to

    produceresentmentand indignation.What requiresclose attention s the process

    that,

    in

    some minds,

    had

    renderedobjectionablethe claims associated with

    the

    existing social system. What had prepared he thirdestate, or at least some of its

    representatives, o construe the nobles' assertions of their social superiorityas

    "condescension and scorn?"

    How,

    within

    the

    context

    of the

    traditional

    social

    order,

    did

    spokesmen

    for the

    thirdestate ever come to believe thatthey were

    enti-

    tled

    to equality? If many members of the third estate had harbored eelings of

    "frustration," humiliation," nd "animosity" owardthe nobility for years, why

    had

    they not condemned

    he

    inequities

    of

    the system in greaternumbersand

    with

    greaterfrequency before 1789? How

    can

    their lingering respect for the institu-

    tion of

    nobility,

    which

    Tackett rightly emphasizes, be reconciled

    with their

    impassioneddenunciations

    of

    the society

    of

    orders

    n

    1789

    and

    after?

    Toanswerall of these questions adequately,one would need to rewritethe his-

    tory of pre-Revolutionarypolitical consciousness in France-an objective far

    beyond

    the

    scope

    of

    a

    journal

    article.

    In

    the

    pages

    that

    remain, however,

    I want

    at

    least to

    begin

    the

    task

    of

    scrutinizing

    the

    long-term thought processes

    that

    enabled the

    future

    revolutionaries

    o

    envision

    peaceful

    and

    multilateral

    political

    reform, on the one hand, and to capture and articulatereasons for powerful

    resentments,

    on the other hand.

    Especially pertinent

    to

    the dramaticconfronta-

    tions of the

    early

    Revolution

    are the diverse opinions concerninghierarchy,

    ta-

    tus,

    and

    the social

    order

    articulated

    between

    roughly

    1750 and

    1789.40

    These

    opinions, expressed by many

    members

    of both the second and third

    estates,

    and

    written or

    variouspurposes,make clear

    the

    contestation

    hat

    surrounded

    he idea

    of

    nobility

    in

    the

    years leading up

    to the Revolution. The

    variety

    of

    the

    views

    expressed, ranging

    from

    reactionary

    assertions of noble

    power

    to bold affirma-

    39. To supporthis account, Tackettcites many instancesof bitternessand resentmenton the part

    of

    the

    deputies.

    The

    deputy

    Jean-Gabriel

    Gallot,

    for

    example, adopted

    an

    exceptionally

    strident

    one.

    In a letter to his wife, he wrote of the noble deputies, "After their abominablebehavior, this noble

    scum, with all their coats of arms, deserves to

    be

    humiliated" 109). The Lyon deputy Jean-Andre

    P6risse Du Luc reportedconfrontingone of his fellow freemasons, a noble of conservative political

    persuasion,with the declaration hat "hereditary obility was a political monstrosity" 110).

    40. For indicationsof this ferment n social thought,see Smith, "Social Categories;" ohn Shovlin,

    "Towarda Reinterpretation f RevolutionaryAntinobilism:The Political Economy of Honor

    in

    the

    Old Regime", Journal of ModernHistory 72 (2000), 35-66; and Rafe Blaufarb,"Noble Privilege

    and

    Absolutist State Building: French Military Administration after the Seven Years' War," French

    Historical Studies 24 (2001), 223-246.

    This content downloaded from 130.63.180.147 on Wed, 29 Apr 2015 15:40:05 UTCAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/23/2019 Jay Smith French Revolution Agency and Ideas

    15/28

    BETWEENDISCOURSEAND EXPERIENCE 129

    tions of the equality of all citizens, make it difficult to believe that the future

    deputies to the Estates-General could have entered the period of pre-

    Revolutionary urmoil utterly unawareof the potential for intransigenceon the

    part

    of

    their

    political opponents.

    Yet

    the

    open-endedness,

    he

    conceptualfluidity,

    and the multivalency of the proposals communicated n the pre-Revolutionary

    decades also suggest that the key issue that separated he deputies of the second

    and

    thirdestates-the natureof the differencebetween noble and non-noble sta-

    tus-remained far from settled

    in

    most

    minds

    down to the early stages of

    the

    constitutional

    crisis of

    1788-1789.

    The events of

    1789

    were

    implicit

    in the

    polit-

    ical

    consciousness

    of the

    Old Regime, but

    it

    was only the

    acceleratedreevalua-

    tion of prioritiesand the

    refinement

    of varying

    structures f

    belief,

    that made

    the

    conflicts of

    that

    year finally

    unavoidable.

    II. BALANCING IDEAS AND ENGAGINGTHE WORLD:

    THEEVOLVINGMIND OF J.-M.-A. SERVAN

    The writings of Joseph-Michel-AntoineServan provide an ideal point of entry

    into the evolving political consciousness of the pre-Revolutionary nd Revolu-

    tionaryyears. On the one hand, his own political trajectory

    n

    1788-1789 seems

    to exemplify

    the

    process charted by Tackett.

    A

    champion of the constitutional

    claims of the third

    estate,

    Servan

    nitially sought

    common

    ground

    with

    the nobil-

    ity before becoming embittered n December 1788.41Angered by what he clear-

    ly perceived as noble arrogance,

    he wrote a

    series of pamphletsfiercely critical

    of the Second Estate

    in

    1789,

    and he

    fully supported

    he

    revolutionary

    nitiatives

    in

    June of that year.

    In

    other words, the path Servan followed

    in

    "becoming"a

    revolutionary eems to have paralleled

    that described

    by Tackett

    n his

    analysis

    of the

    deputies

    to

    the Estates-General.But

    on

    the other

    hand,

    the evidence illu-

    minating

    Servan's life

    and mind in the

    years

    before

    1788

    makes

    it

    difficult

    to

    attributehis radicalization ither

    to

    the

    experience

    of his own social stationunder

    the Old Regime or to the experienceof political debatein 1788-1789. Although

    Servan

    clearly

    identified

    with the third

    estate,

    both as

    an

    authorand as a

    politi-

    cal

    figure, he actually

    came from a

    Dauphinois family

    of minor but

    securely

    established

    nobility.42

    As a

    respectedmagistrate

    n

    the

    parlement

    of

    Grenoble,

    he

    41. For an example of Servan's moderationbefore

    late 1788, see Petit

    colloque

    limnentaire

    ntre

    Mr. A et Mr. B. Sur les abus, le droit, la raison, les Etats-Giniraux,

    les parlements &

    tout

    ce qui

    s'ensuit. Par un vieuxjurisconsulte allobroge (n. p., 1788). The interlocutorsof the pamphletappeal

    to the conscience of both the

    First and

    Second

    Estates and remainhopeful that the.privilegedorders

    will see that the common interest demands an end to fiscal abuses.

    42. Servan's father, he owner of a modest seigneurie, sent his two sons into the customarynoble

    professions of the

    law

    and the military.Despite

    being placed in the conventional career paths of the

    socially ascendant,both

    Servan and his

    younger

    brother,Joseph Servan de Gerbey, actually acquired

    theirreputationsby thepen, calling for theenlightenedreformof theirown respective institutionsand

    for the overall regeneration f

    French

    society. Both

    became enthusiasticsupporters f the Revolution;

    Servan de

    Gerbey would go on

    to serve as Ministerof War n 1792. For background, ee Biographie

    universelle ancienne et moderne, ed.

    Joseph-Frangois

    Michaud,45 vols. (Paris:A. T. Desplaces,

    1854-1865), 39: 139-142; Dictionnaire historique de la revolutionfrancaise, ed. Albert Soboul

    (Paris:Presses

    universitaires

    de France, 1989), 981;

    Dictionnaire Napoleion, d. Jean Tulard,

    2

    vols.,

    This content downloaded from 130.63.180.147 on Wed, 29 Apr 2015 15:40:05 UTCAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/23/2019 Jay Smith French Revolution Agency and Ideas

    16/28

    130

    JAY M.

    SMITH

    would have enduredvery little

    condescension or

    scorn in his pre-Revolutionary

    professional life.

    Moreover,analysis of his

    intellectual evolution in

    the decades

    priorto the

    Revolution shows that

    neitherthe ideas nor the passions to

    which he

    gave

    voice in

    1789 derivedsuddenlyfrom the heatof

    unexpected conflicts. The

    political positions

    he

    articulated

    n

    the

    early stages

    of the

    Revolution, though

    clearly more radicalthananythinghe had producedbefore, grewnaturallyout of

    the complex of ideas thathad filled his

    mind and exercised his

    attention or years.

    He had earlier

    refrained rom

    pushing the most anti-aristocratic

    mplications of

    his moral assumptions

    because

    those assumptions had been

    convoluted and at

    least partially

    conflicting. His

    decision to press for full political

    equality

    in

    1789

    reflected the subordinationof

    some of his beliefs, the

    reformulationof others,

    and

    the

    envisioning

    of a

    new

    social

    world whose coherence demanded

    civic

    equality.

    To make sense of Servan's choices in 1789, one needs to understandhis

    immersion

    in

    the moraldebatesand

    conceptual

    experimentation

    hat

    character-

    ized the entire second half

    of the eighteenth century.

    Like many writers of the

    1760s and

    1770s,

    Servan

    sought

    a

    generalmoral reform of

    French

    society,

    and

    this desire

    inspired

    on his

    part

    sustained

    contemplationof the

    propercharacter-

    istics of the citizen.

    Alarmedby the egoism, lassitude,and

    luxury he saw around

    him,

    Servan

    tried

    to inspire patrioticfeeling in the

    French by

    encouraging the

    cultivationof

    privatevirtue. "Private ife is a continual

    esson

    in

    public

    life,"

    he

    wrote in his

    Discours sur les moeurs

    (Discourse on Morals) of 1769.

    Striking

    a

    distinctly

    Rousseauian

    chord,

    Servan

    asserted

    that the citizen

    who

    developed

    sound personalhabits

    inevitably would

    find that

    "his own

    heart

    is his

    legisla-

    tor."43 ervan

    hoped

    to use the

    medium of

    print,

    and the

    "contagion

    of the

    imag-

    ination,"

    to

    impress upon

    all

    well-intentioned men

    (the

    "honnetes

    gens")

    the

    need for moral

    self-discipline

    and

    civic

    spirit.44

    He assumed that the

    revival of

    moralrigor

    and

    French

    patriotism

    n a

    corrupt ighteenthcentury

    required,

    above

    all, stellarexamplesof rectitudeandselflessness thatreadersandcitizensat large

    could learn from and emulate.

    Also like

    many

    of his

    contemporaries,

    Servan

    expressed

    great

    admiration or

    the

    exploits

    of

    patriots

    from ancient

    Greece

    and

    Rome.45

    f

    one could

    only

    trav-

    el

    through

    ime to visit the households of

    Aristides and

    Cato,

    true

    "sanctuariies]

    of

    morals,"

    one could

    "contemplate

    hese

    great

    and virtuousmen" and

    cultivate

    "the immortal desire of

    imitating

    them."46But Servan

    preferred

    to search

    for

    (Paris:Fayard,1999), 2: 766; Dictionnaire Historique et Biographique de la Revolution et de

    lEmpire, 1789-1815,

    ed.

    Jean-Frangois-Eugene

    Robinet,

    2

    vols.

    (Paris:

    Librairie

    historique

    de la

    revolutionet de

    empire, 1899), 2: 749.

    43.

    Joseph-Michel-Antoine

    Servan,

    Discours sur les moeurs

    (Lyon:

    Chez

    Joseph-SulpiceGrabit,

    1769).

    44. Ibid. The audience of "honnetesgens" is identified

    on p. 2;

    the

    "contagionof

    the

    imagination"

    appearson p. 109.

    45. For

    a

    useful

    discussion of

    the main

    features of classical

    republican hinking

    in

    Old

    Regime

    France, see Keith Michael

    Baker, "Transformations f Classical

    Republicanism

    in

    Eighteenth-

    CenturyFrance,"

    Journal of ModernHistory 73 (2001),

    32-53, esp. 35-42.

    46. Servan,Discours sur les moeurs, 30-31.

    This content downloaded from 130.63.180.147 on Wed, 29 Apr 2015 15:40:05 UTCAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/23/2019 Jay Smith French Revolution Agency and Ideas

    17/28

  • 7/23/2019 Jay Smith French Revolution Agency and Ideas

    18/28

    132

    JAYM.SMITH

    The implicit contrast, in Servan's thinking, between the spiritual nobility

    acquiredthrough civic virtues and the legal

    nobility acquiredby

    birth

    or

    titles

    emerges more clearly

    in

    a text written roughly

    a decade after the Discourse on

    Morals.

    In

    the later text,

    a Discourse on

    the

    Progress of

    Human

    Knowledgepre-

    sented to the Academy of Lyon

    in

    1781, Servan

    continued o emphasize the need

    to form virtuous and patriotic citizens. His

    discussion of

    what

    he called "the

    apprenticeship

    f the

    Citizen"

    differed

    in

    subtle ways, however, from the argu-

    ments advanced

    n

    the Discourse

    on

    Morals.

    Good examples and conscious emu-

    lation of

    those

    examples

    still stood out as the indispensable ingredients of the

    moral educationof the citizen, but Servan also drew attention o the mechanisms

    of recognition

    and

    recompense

    that

    are necessary

    to

    sustain

    the citizen's emula-

    tion over time.

    "In

    a

    state,"

    he

    wrote,

    "the artof makingmen is also

    that

    of offer-

    ing merit its just rewards."But "whathave we done

    in

    France?We have sought

    to purchase

    with

    gold

    what we should have rewarded

    with

    a glance of recogni-

    tion; [consequently,]

    he state has exhausted ts

    treasury,

    nd

    qualities

    of heartare

    debased."51 ervanapplauded he king's decision to commission public statues

    of some of France's

    greatest

    men-he

    specifically

    identified the noble

    writers

    and

    jurists Fenelon, l'Hopital, d'Aguesseau,

    and Montesquieu-because the

    building

    of

    public monuments

    revived a

    highly

    effective Roman practice.52The

    ancientshad shown that "a

    great character,

    fter

    observing

    a

    [hero

    on

    a] pedestal,

    can no longer remain bound to the earth;he must raise himself to that higher

    level, or die trying."53

    ervan

    feared, however,

    that the

    king's efforts would

    not

    bear

    fruit

    unless the

    governmentdeveloped

    a more

    general strategy

    for reward-

    ing patriotic

    emulation.

    Within

    the context of

    this

    broad discussion of

    patriotism, elflessness,

    and the

    propermeans of rewarding hem, Servaneventuallybroached he relatedsubjects

    of

    law and

    nobility. "Oh,

    f

    only

    all

    respectable

    men

    (gens

    de

    bien)

    could

    rely

    on

    a

    body of

    laws that

    provide recompense

    for virtue But where are these laws?"

    Servan noted the other common subdivisions of jurisprudence, uch as martial

    law, canon law, and criminal aw, and he expressed exasperationat the absence

    of

    what

    he termed "remunerative

    aw."

    Imagine

    One has to

    create a

    name for

    the

    most noble subject of

    human

    legislation

    We

    have

    neither

    he

    word nor

    the

    thing.

    All

    across Europe

    we have

    signs

    and

    colors

    that

    prove

    that a

    man was born into

    the

    Nobility;

    we have

    others

    that

    prove

    that he served

    in

    the

    army;

    we have othersthat

    prove nothing

    at all.

    But

    by

    what

    signs,

    what

    marks,

    do

    we rec-

    ognize

    the

    enlightened

    zeal of the

    ecclesiastic,

    the

    vigilance

    and

    integrity

    of

    the

    magis-

    trate, heheroic valor of thesoldier,thegood faithof themerchant,he industryof the arti-

    san,

    the

    talent of

    the artist?

    The

    legal

    marks

    of nobility-parchments,

    titles, epaulettes-were always

    clear

    and, moreover, frequently meaningless.

    Other

    "gens

    de

    bien," however,

    fell

    51. Servan, Discours sur le progre'sdes connoissances humaines en general, de la morale, et de

    la legislation en particulier; lu dans une

    Assemblie

    publique de

    l'Acadjmie

    de Lyon (n. p.,

    1781),

    109-110.

    52. Servan,Discours sur le

    progris,

    111.

    53. Ibid., 109.

    This content downloaded from 130.63.180.147 on Wed, 29 Apr 2015 15:40:05 UTCAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/23/2019 Jay Smith French Revolution Agency and Ideas

    19/28

    BETWEENDISCOURSEAND EXPERIENCE

    133

    into a vast and undifferentiated rowd,

    where "all merit s obscured,happymere-

    ly to escape persecution,happier still to

    avoid extinction."54Yet in spite of

    the

    flaws

    in

    the current ystem, Servanreported hat he could "hear he humanheart

    cry out from

    all

    directions:Look at me, and I

    will

    do

    well; praise me,

    and I

    will

    do better." Servan

    argued

    that

    the

    king,

    if he

    wished to

    command "citizens"

    rather han mere "subjects,"must managecarefullythe signs of public esteem so

    that

    genuine

    merit and

    civic virtueswould receive the encouragement nd recog-

    nition they needed. By dispensing

    official honors widely, conspicuously, and

    fairly, the king would inspire in his

    subjects a "deliriousenthusiasm"and help to

    provide "public nstruction" n the virtues

    of citizenship.That last point deserved

    emphasis, because "good public

    education"

    was

    "the only plank left

    amid the

    universal shipwreckof morals"

    confrontingFrench society.55

    The Discours of 1781 can be seen as

    an

    elaboration

    of

    ideas first

    expressed

    in

    the Discours of 1769. The ultimateobjective of both texts is to reformboth indi-

    vidual morals and the broaderpolitical

    cultureof

    the

    eighteenthcentury.Servan

    hoped to replace luxury and egoism with civic spirit and virtue, and to that end,

    he used both of his texts to highlightappropriate bjects of emulation or the con-

    scientious citizen-ancient patriots,

    statuesof greatmen,

    and

    the

    heroic and

    hon-

    orable nobility of earlier centuries.

    In

    both of his

    discourses, moreover,

    Servan

    looked past the standardcategories of

    profession or estate to address

    all

    right-

    minded citizens, the "honnetes gens"

    in

    1769, the neglected "gens de bien" in

    1781.

    In

    short, the purposes and generalcharacteristics f the moral reform

    that

    Servancraved

    changed

    not at

    all between 1769

    and

    1781;

    the two

    discourses

    dif-

    fered

    only

    in the

    techniques

    of

    reform

    that

    they

    recommended.

    In

    1769,

    Servan

    had encouragedself-examinationand patriotic

    ntrospection.56 y 1781,

    he had

    become

    persuaded

    hat

    the

    "contagion

    of the

    imagination"

    on

    which he had ear-

    lier based his hopes also needed

    structural einforcement.Individualgood

    will

    and initiative

    remained

    important,

    but

    the

    monarchy's

    methods of

    recognizing

    excellence had

    to change

    to accommodate

    he

    broad

    imperative

    of

    forming

    vir-

    tuous

    and

    patrioticcitizens. Whereas the Discourse

    on morals worked from the

    ground up by urging readersto strive for

    a nobility of virtue

    in

    their

    own

    lives,

    the Discourse on

    the

    progress of

    human

    knowledge

    worked

    from the other direc-

    tion

    and urged

    the crown to

    acknowledge formally

    the

    demonstrated

    piritual

    nobility

    of the

    patriot.

    Given his

    penchant

    or inclusive

    rhetoric,

    and

    his own

    apparentability

    to craft

    a kind of

    hybrid

    moral

    dentity,

    how

    should Servan'scontributions

    o the debates

    of 1789 be understood?Although he had previously shown no overt hostility

    54. Ibid., 107.

    55. Ibid., 124-125.

    56. Moral self-reliance s one of the overriding hemes of the Discours sur les moeurs.

    After detail-

    ing the plentiful evidence of

    modern

    corruption, Servan lamented that

    "all

    the

    wisdom of the

    Government s

    powerless

    in

    the face of evils so great. How unjustwe are We accuse

    those who gov-

    ern us [of moral failure],

    and

    yet

    we fail

    to see

    that

    their faults are

    our own"

    (52).

    He had opened the

    discourse

    by distinguishing

    morals

    [moeurs]

    rom mere positive law, which

    he

    claimed

    had

    only

    lim-

    ited effects on behavior."Morals,"he wrote, "are the true foundationof the prosperity

    of Empires;

    morals can accomplish anything,even without laws, but laws without moralscan do nothing" 2).

    This content downloaded from 130.63.180.147 on Wed, 29 Apr 2015 15:40:05 UTCAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/23/2019 Jay Smith French Revolution Agency and Ideas

    20/28

    134 JAY M.

    SMITH

    towardthe Second Estate, his

    writings of the

    "pre-Revolution" stablished an

    unmistakable nd

    uncharacteristic hetoricaloppositionbetween the nobility and

    commoners.In

    one piece he identified

    himself,

    with

    mock

    humility,and

    a

    certain

    disingenuousness,as a "mere

    bourgeois."57Another

    essay bore the title "com-

    mentary

    of a commoner."58 everalpamphletsdecried

    the "dangerousaristocra-

    cy" of the high nobility andmagistracy.59n a pamphlet hat addressed he polit-

    ical

    interestsof the thirdestate,

    he expresseddisdainfor "thosewho dareto scorn

    you."60

    Servan's

    steady

    stream

    of anti-aristocratic hetoric

    in

    1789

    no

    doubt

    helps to

    explain why he was chosen by two

    different electoral districts of

    Dauphine to represent the third

    estate of his province at

    the coming Estates-

    General,

    an

    honorhe

    politely

    declined.6'What

    explains

    the

    change

    in

    tone? Were

    Servan's

    fighting words

    produced by the shock of political conflict?His pam-

    phlets

    certainly commented on

    and responded to dramaticevents, such as the

    declarationsof the second Assembly of Notables, and the Parlementof Paris's

    announcementof its

    support or the Notables' conservative constitutional

    argu-

    ments.

    2

    If one focused strictly

    on the apparentpolitical

    dynamics of the year

    1789,

    one could

    well

    interpret

    Servan's heated

    rhetoric

    as

    reflecting

    a

    change

    of

    consciousnessbroughtabout by

    stunningevents and

    unanticipated xperiences.

    Butjust as

    Servan's critique of

    French

    laws in

    1781 had reflected his specific

    and

    personal

    preoccupationwith the challenge of

    cultivating citizenship

    in an

    age of

    corruption, so

    his

    interventions

    in

    the constitutional debates of 1789

    reflectedthe fermentationandevolution of his own thoughtson the political and

    social order.Some

    of the vocabularyemployed

    in

    his

    argumentsmay

    have been

    providedby the immediate

    issues that framed the

    conflict-"aristocracy" and

    "commoners,""despotism"

    and

    "abuses"-but the

    perspective

    communicated

    n

    Servan's

    pamphlets

    was

    perfectly

    consistent

    with,

    and had

    obviously grown

    from,

    attitudeshe had

    express